Sichos In English   Holidays  Shabbat   Calendar  ×‘×´×”

     Sichos In English -> Books -> Parshah -> Likkutei Sichot - Volume X - Devarim
Volume 6   |   Volume 7   |   Volume 8   |   Volume 9   |   Volume 10
   

Translator's Foreword

Devarim

   Devarim

Vaes'chanan

Eikev

Chof Menachem Av

Re'eh

Shoftim

Ki Seitzei

Ki Savo

Chai Elul

Nitzavim

Rosh HaShanah

Vayeilech

Yom Kippur

Haazinu

Sukkos

Simchas Torah

Founders of Chassidism & Leaders of Chabad-Lubavitch

Glossary

Likkutei Sichot - Volume X - Devarim
An Anthology of Talks Relating to the weekly sections of
the Torah and Special occasions in the Jewish calendar
by the Lubavitcher Rebbe Rabbi Menachem M. Schneerson


Ki Seitzei

English rendition by Rabbi Eliyahu Touger

Published and copyright © by Sichos In English
(718) 778-5436   •   info@SichosInEnglish.org   •   FAX (718) 735-4139


Add to Shopping Cart   |   Buy this nowFor Palm Pilot
  ShoftimKi Savo  

When Should One Divorce?

The Talmud mentions[221] several opinions regarding when it is appropriate for a man to divorce his wife:

The School of Shammai say: "A man should not divorce his wife unless he discovers immodest conduct...."
The School of Hillel say: "[He may divorce her] even if she [intentionally][222] spoiled his food."
Rabbi Akiva says: "[He may divorce her] even if he finds another one who is more attractive, as it is written:[223] 'If she does not find favor in his eyes....' "
Although there are some exceptions,[224] the School of Hillel generally rule more leniently than the School of Shammai. For the souls of the School of Shammai stem from the attribute of judgment, which tends toward stringency and view many things as unable to be elevated. Therefore they may not be used in our Divine service.

The souls of the School of Hillel, by contrast, stem from the attribute of kindness, which seeks to find that spark of good in every entity that allows it to be elevated to the realm of holiness.[225]

On one hand, permission to divorce one's wife is a leniency. Nevertheless, it is not an expression of the attribute of kindness. Divorce stems from rigor and severity, and leads to distance and division.[226] The attribute of kindness, by contrast, is identified with love and opposes divorce. Why then does the School of Hillel make the process of divorce more accessible than the School of Shammai?

A similar question can be asked with regard to Rabbi Akiva. He is also identified with kindness, as reflected in his efforts to seek the merit of the Jewish people.[227] Why does he allow for divorce even when a husband finds another woman more attractive than his wife?

These questions become even stronger when we consider that the relationship between men and women is an analogy for the relationship between G-d and the Jews.[228] The opinions of the School of Shammai, the School of Hillel, and Rabbi Akiva thus have implications in our people's relationship with G-d.[229]

With regard to the spiritual counterpart of divorce, the willingness to countenance such a drastic measure is surely an expression of the attribute of judgment. Why then do the School of Hillel rule more stringently than the School of Shammai? And why does Rabbi Akiva, who seeks the merit of the Jewish people, rule that even when there are no shortcomings in a woman's (i.e. a Jew's) conduct, her husband (G-d) may divorce her if He so chooses?

Fulfilling One's Personal Mission

The relationship between men and women serves as an analogy, not only for the bond between G-d and the Jewish people, but also for the relationship between the body and soul. The soul is "an actual part of G-d"[230] and therefore is referred to as "a man," while the body -- and by extension, a person's mission in the world at large -- is referred to as a woman.[231]

Every soul has a mission which it was charged to fulfill in this world.[232] And "the steps of man are ordered by G-d."[233] Wherever a Jew is found, he must realize that he was sent by Divine Providence as part of his or her mission to make the world a dwelling for G-d.

Even when confronted with difficulties in his path of Divine service, including some that make it appear that another path will enable him to achieve more, a person should not necessarily abandon his original course. It is the path which Divine Providence has granted him; this is his mission.

As mentioned above, a soul and its mission can be described using the analogy of a husband and a wife. On this basis, we can explain the differences of opinion between the Sages mentioned above. The question is: When should one abandon -- divorce -- one's mission to refine one's portion of the world and accept another mission?[234]

The School of Shammai maintains that "a person should not divorce his wife unless he discovers immodest conduct...." Regardless of the obstacles he faces, one may not abandon the path of Divine service with which he has been charged. He should not be troubled by the obstacles he faces, for if he perseveres, he will ultimately succeed.

When should he change? When there is "immodest conduct" -- a clear directive from the Shulchan Aruch that he is forbidden to continue in this path of Divine service (just as when a woman acts immodestly, her husband is forbidden to remain married to her). In such an instance, one must find a different path of service.

(His previous path of service will then be allotted to another soul. This is also alluded to in the Torah, which states[235] that the divorced woman "will become the wife of another man.")

The School of Hillel are more lenient, allowing a person to pick a new path of Divine service when "his food is spoiled." The implication is that not only is the person not successful in his mission to refine his portion of the world, but "his food," the spiritual attainments of the soul, have become spoiled. In such an instance, one may accept another path of Divine service.

Rabbi Akiva maintains that divorce is possible "even if he finds another one who is more attractive." Even when there is no lack in a person's service, nor a deficiency in his internal powers, if his path of Divine service "no longer finds favor in his eyes," i.e., he has lost his zeal for it, he may accept another. (chein, translated as favor, relates to the attribute of pleasure, and refers to a person's encompassing powers.[236])

Rabbi Akiva's rationale is that a Jew must carry out his Divine service with joy.[237] Therefore when he lacks zeal, he can exchange his previous path for one which he finds more attractive.

Beyond the Measure of the Law

The halachah follows the opinion of the School of Hillel.[238] This means that when a person's Divine service does not lack anything, but he has lost his zeal for it, he may not abandon his path. But if "his food is spoiled," and his previous attainments are being marred, the law allows him to seek another path.

This, however, reflects merely the letter of the law. Our Sages state:[239] "Whenever a man divorces his first wife, even the altar sheds tears for him," and[240] "How difficult is divorce!" The implication is that a person should persevere in the path of Divine service with which he was charged[241] to the limit of his endurance.

Even if he has divorced his wife (that is, if he abandoned his previous path of Divine service) he should remarry her, returning to take up his burden again.[242]

Moreover, even if "he discovered immodest conduct," it is not fitting for him to hurry to divorce his first wife.[243] Instead, he should investigate the matter thoroughly to see whether or not there was in fact immodest conduct.

In the analog, this means that even if it appears to him that Torah law requires him to abandon his previous path of Divine service, he should not make the decision hastily. Perhaps he is being influenced by self-love, and it only appears to him that another path of Divine service would be easier. When he investigates the matter, he may realize that it is preferable for him to persevere. And when he dedicates himself to the matter with all the powers of his soul, then as a result -- "when a man and a woman merit, the Divine Presence will rest between them,"[244] in the analog, the soul will merit the consummation of its service, the establishment of a dwelling for G-d in this world.

(Adapted from Sichos Chof Menachem Av, 5719)

An Insight Into the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch

Parshas Ki Seitzei also contains the command:[245] "Do not muzzle an ox while it is threshing," which prohibits preventing an ox -- or any other animal[246] -- from eating the grain it is threshing.

The Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch (printed by the Mitteler Rebbe and his brothers) spells out the laws involved in this prohibition. The last law states:

When cows are passing over grain while taking a shortcut [to another field], a person does not transgress the prohibition "Do not muzzle" if he muzzles them. Although as a matter of course, the grain is threshed as they pass over it, since this is not his intent, [no prohibition is involved]. The same applies in other similar instances.
As mentioned on several occasions, the wording used by the Alter Rebbe in his Shulchan Aruch is very precise. By carefully analyzing his phrasing, it is possible to gain new insights.

The source for the Alter Rebbe's ruling is a teaching of the Rambam which states:[247] "When cows are passing over grain while taking a shortcut, a person does not transgress the prohibition 'Do not muzzle' [if he muzzles them]." The Alter Rebbe, however, makes several measured additions to the Rambam's wording.

  1. The phrase "although as a matter of course, the grain is threshed as they pass over it" is not found in the Rambam's words. The reason for the addition can be explained as follows: It is possible to interpret the Rambam's words as meaning that the leniency is granted only when the cows do not thresh as they passed over the grain.[248] (Even this would be considered a leniency; since the cattle are going to thresh in another field, one might think that passing through this field would also be considered part of the task of threshing, and it would be forbidden to muzzle them.) The Alter Rebbe makes the above addition[249] to make it clear that the leniency includes even an instance when grain is threshed as they pass.

  2. The rationale the Alter Rebbe gives -- "since this is not his intent" -- is not mentioned by the halachic authorities of previous generations. For example, the Ramban[250] quotes the Jerusalem Talmud,[251] which states that the prohibition applies "while 'threshing,' and not while passing through." It appears that the Alter Rebbe considers the prohibition, not as a "Scriptural decree," but as a teaching motivated by a rationale, "since this is not his intent."

  3. The Alter Rebbe concludes with the phrase: "The same applies in other similar instances." Apparently, these words come to complement the concept mentioned previously: that the leniency does not come about because of a "Scriptural decree," but because the person acted unintentionally. And so, the Alter Rebbe continues, whenever a person acts unintentionally, he is not held liable.

This concept is a matter of debate among the halachic authorities. The Sheiltos D'Rav Achai Gaon states[252] that only with regard to the laws of Shabbos is a person not held liable for committing a transgression unintentionally. With regard to the Shabbos laws, we find the principle:[253] "It is thoughtful labor which the Torah prohibited." When a person performs an act unintentionally, he has not performed "thoughtful labor," and therefore is not held liable.[254] With regard to other prohibitions, by contrast, even when a person does not perform an act with the intent of violating a Torah prohibition, if such a violation occurs, he is held liable.

Most halachic authorities maintain that even when a person violates other prohibitions unintentionally, he is not liable. This is the intent of the Alter Rebbe's phrase "The same applies in other similar instances."

What Constitutes an Unintentional Activity

A person is not held liable for an action performed unintentionally only when that action does not necessarily cause the prohibition to be performed. When, however, he intentionally performs an act which will inevitably cause a prohibition to be transgressed, he is held liable. To cite the classic example employed by the Talmud:[255] It is forbidden to slaughter an animal on the Shabbos. Even when one does not desire to slaughter a chicken, but wants to cut off its head for another reason, one is liable for slaughter. For when its head is cut off, it will surely die. It thus cannot be said that it was slaughtered unintentionally.

According to this principle, a difficulty arises. In the instance cited by the Alter Rebbe, although the person who causes the cows to pass over the field did not intend that they thresh the grain, it is inevitable that the grain will be threshed. Should he not therefore be held liable for muzzling his cows?

This leads to a redefinition of the above concept. When is a person who does something that inevitably leads to a violation of the law liable? When the activity he himself performs causes the violation. For example, when a person drags heavy furniture over the ground, it will surely leave a groove. Although he did not intend to dig that groove, it is inevitable that the activity will cause the groove to be dug, so it is considered as if the groove was dug intentionally.[256]

Similar concepts apply to other prohibitions. For example, it is forbidden for a person afflicted by tzaraas[257] to remove a mark of that malady. If such a person has such a mark on his shoulder, and carries a rod which will certainly remove that mark, one might think that he is liable, even though he did not intend to remove the mark. Therefore a special teaching is necessary[258] to tell us that carrying a rod is permitted in such an instance. Although his intention was not to remove the mark, since carrying the rod would inevitably bring about the mark's removal, it cannot be said that he did not intentionally remove it.

A distinction can thus be made with regard to the muzzling of cows mentioned above. In this instance, the activity which will inevitably be performed does not involve muzzling (which constitutes the prohibition), but rather threshing. The threshing itself is permitted; the Torah merely tells us not to muzzle an animal while it is threshing. Since the threshing itself is not prohibited, the conception of an inevitable activity does not apply, and the threshing is considered unintentional. Therefore the prohibition against muzzling is not violated.[259]

The above leads to a new definition of the Alter Rebbe's words. To explain: Just as there is a prohibition: "Do not muzzle an ox while threshing," there is also a prohibition: "Do not thresh with a muzzled ox."[260] Based on the above, it would appear that only when a person muzzles his cows as they are passing over grain is he not liable for threshing with a muzzled cow, because the cows are passing over the grain without an intention to thresh it. For then the cows are walking on their own initiative, [it is not he who is causing them to walk]. But if he muzzled the cows beforehand, and then caused them to walk over grain, it is inevitable that a forbidden activity will be performed. Therefore one commits the transgression even though one had no intention to thresh.

One might ask: why doesn't the Alter Rebbe spell this concept out explicitly? Why doesn't he say that it is only when one muzzles the cows afterwards that one is not liable?

It is possible to explain that in his Shulchan Aruch, the Alter Rebbe follows the pattern established by the Rambam in the Mishneh Torah. Rarely -- except in the relatively few instances which he states "It appears to me" -- does the Rambam mention laws at which he arrived through his own deductive reasoning. It is true that the Alter Rebbe, unlike the Rambam, adds the motivating principles for the laws, and this allows for several new laws to be derived. He does not, however, mention those new laws explicitly.

For this reason, he does not explicitly state the implications of muzzling cows before they start walking or afterwards;[261] he merely states the reason one is not liable -- because one's act is performed unintentionally.

Together with the motivating principle, the Alter Rebbe also adds the phrase: "The same applies in other similar instances," teaching that whenever one violates a transgression unintentionally, one is not liable. This statement allows for inferences to be drawn in both directions. Just as it teaches that a person who unintentionally violates other transgressions is not liable, it implies that the definitions of unintentional activity as applied to other prohibitions also apply to the prohibition against muzzling oxen. And thus we can understand that whether or not the prohibition applies depends on whether the cows were muzzled before they tread on the grain or afterwards.

The Advantage of Analytic Study

As mentioned above, we must study the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch in detail, thinking deeply about the wording he uses[262] and assessing the meaning of his phrasing. This will lead to many new insights both regarding the halachah at hand and other related -- and seemingly unrelated -- concepts. For example, in the law mentioned above, the Alter Rebbe conveys several concepts in the measured words he chose:

  1. The person does not transgress the prohibition despite the fact that the grain is threshed.

  2. The reason he is not liable is because the act was performed unintentionally.

  3. He is not liable only when it is not inevitable that the grain will be threshed.

  4. The concept that one is not liable for a transgression violated unintentionally applies, not only with regard to the laws of Shabbos (as stated in the Sheiltos), but also with regard to all the prohibitions in the Torah.

May G-d grant that we study the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch and the Tanya in depth, particularly in the present year, the 150th anniversary of his passing. This applies to the study of Nigleh, the revealed dimension of Torah law, and Chassidus. May we labor in Torah study, employing our three intellectual faculties: Chochmah, Binah, and Daas. And then we will merit the fulfillment of our Sages' promise:[263] "If you labor, you will discover."

The word "discover" implies that a person will receive incomparably more than he invests. For a discovery cannot be attained through effort. Instead, "a discovery comes when one's attention is diverted."[264]

Indeed, the Torah will then be granted to the person as a present, and become his eternally. In this vein, we find a teaching of our Sages:[265] Before G-d gave Moshe the Torah as a present, he would forget. Once He granted him the Torah as a present, however, he did not forget.

Tying the End to the Beginning

It is Jewish custom to connect the end of a Torah text[266] with its beginning.[267] The Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch begins with the laws of rising in the morning, stating:[268]

Yehudah ben Teima says:[269] "Be bold as a leopard, light as an eagle... to carry out the will of your Father in Heaven."
Herein lies a connection to the conclusion of the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch. As mentioned above, the last words, the phrase "the same applies in other similar instances," teaches that a person's freedom from liability for an unintentional violation is not a Scriptural decree applying only to muzzling an animal, or only with regard to the laws of Shabbos, but rather is a general principle applying to all Torah prohibitions.

There is a difference of opinion among our Sages as to whether having the proper intention when fulfilling mitzvos is an absolute imperative, or if it is acceptable, after the fact, that mitzvos are fulfilled without the proper intent.[270]

According to most authorities,[271] there are certain types of mitzvos which -- after the fact -- do not require[272] an intention to fulfill the mitzvah.[273] Furthermore, there are some mitzvos which a person fulfills even when compelled to perform them against his will.

This indicates that there is a fundamental difference between a mitzvah and a transgression. When a person violates a prohibition unintentionally, he is not considered to have transgressed, while when he performs a mitzvah unintentionally, he is still considered to have fulfilled the mitzvah.

Why is there a difference? Moreover, if a difference exists, one would think that the opposite would be true. Mitzvos are acts of connection to G-d, binding both the person who fulfills them and the physical objects employed. A transgression, by contrast, separates the person and the objects involved from G-d.

Physical entities -- and the body and animal soul of a Jew[274] -- are under the dominion of kelipas nogah, the spiritual gestalt dominating our world, which is primarily -- so much so that one can almost say entirely -- entirely evil.[275] Thus the body and material existence are closer to evil than to good.

It would appear that to separate material entities from G-dliness is far easier than to establish a connection with Him. Why is it that to create separation an intent is necessary, while a connection with G-d can be established without having any intention?

This question is resolved by the Alter Rebbe's words at the beginning of the Shulchan Aruch: "The Laws of Rising in the Morning: Be bold as a leopard... to carry out the will of your Father in heaven." When a Jew begins his day by reciting Modeh Ani and thus establishing a connection with G-d, he causes that connection to encompass the entire day. Therefore even if he does not intend to perform a mitzvah at another time during the day, the bond with G-d established through the performance of the mitzvah is effected by the commitment he made at the beginning of the day.

To cite a parallel: Before consecrating a woman, a man must declare his intent, telling her that he is consecrating her by giving her a coin (or an article worth money). If, however, a man and a woman were discussing marriage before he gave her the coin, and he gave it to her without making an explicit statement, the consecration is effective.[276] We assume that his act is an expression of the statements made previously.

This motif does not apply with regard to transgressions. As long as a person does not intend to perform the transgression, he is not considered to have sinned. Firstly, his deed lacks the intent that causes it to be considered a sin; it is like a body without a soul.[277]

Moreover, since the person began his day by saying Modeh Ani or the like, there is a subconscious motivation leading him away from sin all day. For this reason, an unintentional act cannot be considered a sin. To cite a parallel: Even those opinions which maintain that after the fact it is not necessary to have the intention of performing a mitzvah agree that if one has the opposite intent -- i.e., if one intends to not perform the mitzvah while in fact performing it -- one has not fulfilled his obligation.[278]

To apply the above concept with regard to a transgression: The commitment to serve G-d made at the beginning of the day continues throughout the day. Thus if one unintentionally transgresses, it is not considered a sin, because the underlying intent of all one's actions is to serve G-d.

Of Universal Relevance

A question, however, arises: The laws that state that by performing the deed, one is considered to have fulfilled a mitzvah even though one did not intend to do so, and that one is not liable for a transgression which is performed unintentionally apply to all Jews, even those who do not begin their day by making a commitment to serve G-d. How can we explain the difference between mitzvos and transgressions for such individuals?

We can understand why such a person is not liable for performing a transgression unintentionally. Although his general approach is that of rejecting the yoke of G-d's mitzvos, that underlying approach is not considered to motivate any particular act (as explained above with regard to the consecration of a woman). For there is no unity in the realm of kelipah, and every action is considered isolated from every other.[279]

Why, however, is a person whose general approach is not to accept G-d's will considered to have fulfilled a mitzvah when he performed the deed without any such intent? Seemingly, it is inappropriate to say that his underlying intent is to fulfill G-d's will.

Such a perspective fails to recognize the true nature of a Jew. The inner desire of every Jew is to do good.[280] Although this desire may be hidden in the subconscious, it still motivates the person's conduct.[281] Therefore, the motif described above with regard to the consecration of a woman can be said to apply here as well.

To cite an example: When a priest offers a sacrifice without the proper intent, the sacrifice is acceptable because "the heart of the court has their intent in mind."[282] Since every Jew shares a connection to the court and its rulings, the intent of the court is sufficient, and it is considered as if the priests had this intent themselves.[283]

Following this pattern, it can be explained that proper intent is not necessary when performing a mitzvah because every Jew shares a connection to his spiritual core. Therefore even when he performs a mitzvah without proper intent, he is giving over his inner will to G-d and establishing a connection between Him and his body.

To state the most cosmic expressions of this motif: At present, we are consecrated to G-d. This bond will have a continuing effect, leading to the ultimate marriage, the fulfillment of the prophecy:[284] "On that day... you shall say 'My Man,' and you will no longer say 'My Master,'" with the coming of Mashiach in the immediate future.

(Adapted from Sichos Chof Daled Teves, 5723)

   

Notes:

  1. (Back to text) Gittin 90a.

  2. (Back to text) The bracketed additions are based on the Tur (Even HaEzer, ch. 119) and the commentary of the Meiri to Gittin, loc. cit.

  3. (Back to text) Devarim 24:1.

  4. (Back to text) As annotated in the Mishnah, Ediyos, chs. 4 and 5.

  5. (Back to text) Zohar, Vol. III, p. 245a; Taamei HaMitzvos by Rav Chayim Vital, Parshas Ki Seitzei; Shaar HaGilgulim, Hakdamah 36; Tanya, Iggeres HaKodesh, Epistle 13; Likkutei Torah, Shir HaShirim, p. 40a, 45c.

  6. (Back to text) See Bava Basra 160b.

  7. (Back to text) Rashi, Sanhedrin 110b, entry Shavkinen.

  8. (Back to text) As reflected in the interpretations of Shir HaShirim. See the sichah to Parshas Metzora in this series, which speaks of this concept.

  9. (Back to text) For example, the prophet Yeshayahu employs the metaphor of divorce, asking (50:1): "Where is your mother's bill of divorce?" See also the maamar entitled Eichah, 5670 (printed in Reshimos al Megilas Eichah, p. 52).

  10. (Back to text) Iyov 31:2, as cited by Tanya, ch. 2, which adds the word mamash ("actual"). See the introduction to Shefa Tal.

  11. (Back to text) See Zohar, Vol. I, p. 122b ff.; the commentary of Rabbeinu Bachaye to Bereishis 3:21. See also the sichah entitled Kol HaYotzei l'Milchemes Beis David [(Likkutei Dibburim, Vol. IV, p. 1578) English Translation: With Light and With Might.]

  12. (Back to text) This brings about the union between the Kadosh Baruch Hu (the aspect of G-d associated with the level of Za'er Anpin) and the Shechinah (the aspect of G-d associated with the level of Malchus). A lack of Divine service causes the opposite: the spiritual counterpart of divorce. This reflects the connection between this interpretation and the preceding one.

  13. (Back to text) Tehillim 37:23. See HaYom Yom, entry Tammuz 10.

  14. (Back to text) For divorce is connected with remarriage, since a man who divorces his wife is obliged to marry another woman.

  15. (Back to text) Devarim 24:2.

  16. (Back to text) There are differences between chein translated as "favor," and yofi, translated as "beauty." Beauty refers to a person's outward appearance and physical form (see Rashi's interpretation of Bereishis 29:17: "Of beautiful form and appearance." See also the interpretation of that verse in Torah Or). It thus relates to a person's internal powers.

    Favor, by contrast, relates to a person's encompassing powers. (See Sotah 47a which states: "There are three types of favor..." and the Maamar entitled Vayihi Omen, 5627.) Rabbi Akiva maintains that even when the only thing the soul lacks is the influence of its encompassing powers, it may seek a new path of Divine service.

  17. (Back to text) Rambam, Mishneh Torah, the conclusion of Hilchos Lulav; Tanya, ch. 26.

  18. (Back to text) Tur and Shulchan Aruch (Even HaEzer, ch. 119:3).

  19. (Back to text) Gittin 90b.

  20. (Back to text) Sanhedrin 22a.

  21. (Back to text) In particular, this applies with regard to the first path of Divine service (his "first wife"), which his soul was assigned when it descended to this earth.

  22. (Back to text) As it is fitting for a person to remarry his former wife (Sefer HaChinuch, mitzvah 580).

  23. (Back to text) Rambam, Mishneh Torah, Hilchos Geirushin 10:21. It appears that this applies even if he discovered immodest conduct, as stated by the Chelkas Mechokeik 119:2. Note, however, the interpretations of the Bayis Chadash to the Tur (Even HaEzer, ch. 119), and the gloss of the Beis Shmuel 119:3.

  24. (Back to text) Sotah 17a.

  25. (Back to text) Devarim 25:4.

  26. (Back to text) Bava Kamma 54b; Shulchan Aruch HaRav, Choshen Mishpat, Hilchos Shaaleh U'Sechiros VeChasimah, law 22.

  27. (Back to text) Mishneh Torah, Hilchos Sechirus 13:4.

  28. (Back to text) See the Shitah Mekubetzes (in the name of the Ritba), Bava Metzia 89b; Minchas Chinuch, mitzvah 596.

  29. (Back to text) See the Mishneh LiMelech, who offers a similar interpretation.

  30. (Back to text) In his commentary to Bava Metzia, quoted by the Maggid Mishneh to Hilchos Sechirus, loc. cit.

  31. (Back to text) Terumos 9:1.

  32. (Back to text) Sheilta 105.

  33. (Back to text) Beitzah 13b; Chagigah 10b.

  34. (Back to text) Tosafos, entry Talmud, Shabbos 110b.

  35. (Back to text) Shabbos 75a.

  36. (Back to text) Shulchan Aruch HaRav 337:1.

  37. (Back to text) [A physical affliction mentioned in the Torah which some identify with leprosy.]

  38. (Back to text) See Shabbos 133a, which derives this concept from the exegesis of a verse from the Torah.

  39. (Back to text) The above principle can be explained in several ways. Among them:

    a) It is sufficient to posit that the intent of one act -- e.g., cutting off a chicken's head -- will be extended to include the inevitable consequence of that activity. It cannot be extended to involve a third matter.

    To cite a parallel: There is a difference between kocho (the direct result of a person's activity) and koach kocho (an indirect result). [Thus in the above instance, the intent could be extended to involve threshing, but threshing in and of itself is not forbidden.]

    b) In order for an activity (e.g., killing a chicken) to relate to the intent with which another deed is performed (cutting off its head), the first act must be of consequence. To cite a parallel: We find the expression (see Bechoros 10a): "The prohibition caused it to be considered of consequence." [In the above instance, since the threshing is not forbidden, it is not considered of consequence, and therefore is not considered intentional.]

    c) For an activity (e.g., killing a chicken) to be considered as having been performed intentionally, and thus be considered as a transgression, the prohibition must have a direct connection to the person who performed it. In the instance at hand, the person's intent (that the cows pass through the field) and the inevitable result (that the grain is threshed) are both permitted.

    The hypothesis advanced above -- that the threshing is not forbidden although it is inevitable that it will take place -- applies only to the direct result of the act; it is not challenged by the following teaching (Machshirin 4:1):

    When a person bends over to drink [from a stream], [if] the water that remains on his mouth and mustache [later come into contact with produce, the contact is considered] intentional.

    Rabbeinu Asher explains the rationale for this ruling as follows: since it is impossible for a person to drink if the water does not reach his mustache..., [it is considered as if the water was placed there intentionally,] for every consequence that is inevitable is considered as if it was performed intentionally.

    Rabbeinu Asher is saying that the person's intent to drink the water which enters his mouth applies to the water on his mustache as well, although he had no intention that the water on his mustache be lifted [from the stream]. One might think that this does not follow the principle mentioned above, because the produce does not become fit to contract ritual impurity until it comes in contact with the water, and that contact is not a direct result of his drinking.

    A distinction can, nevertheless, be made. When water is removed from the stream, it becomes considered as water which can make an object subject to ritual impurity. This status is conveyed upon the water at once (although it does not have any effect until the water actually comes into contact with produce). As such, the inevitable act (that water was lifted up on his mustache) is directly connected to the status it receives (that it can cause produce to become susceptible to ritual impurity).

    With regard to the instance mentioned above, by contrast, threshing and muzzling are two separate acts, and the threshing itself is not forbidden. It is only when one threshes intentionally that it is forbidden to muzzle an ox.

  40. (Back to text) Bava Metzia 90b; Shulchan Aruch, Choshen Mishpat 338:3.

  41. (Back to text) It is possible to say, however, that this concept is alluded to in the wording used by the Alter Rebbe: "When cows are passing over grain." Seemingly, the intent is that they are already in the process of passing over.

  42. (Back to text) See Likkutei Dibburim, p. 789.

  43. (Back to text) Megillah 6b.

  44. (Back to text) Sanhedrin 97a.

  45. (Back to text) Nedarim 38a.

  46. (Back to text) This sichah was delivered by the Rebbe on Teves 24, the Alter Rebbe's yahrzeit, as a Hadran, concluding address, on the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch.

  47. (Back to text) Perhaps the motivating principle for this relates to the concept (Likkutei Torah, Shir HaShirim, p. 1c): "The end is rooted in the beginning, and the beginning in the end."

  48. (Back to text) This is the beginning of the revision (Mahadura Tenyana) of the Alter Rebbe's Shulchan Aruch. The original text also begins in a similar fashion.

  49. (Back to text) Avos 5:20.

  50. (Back to text) See Shulchan Aruch HaRav, the conclusion of sec. 65. See the conclusion of Ateres Rosh for an explanation of both views according to the teachings of Chassidus.

  51. (Back to text) See S'dei Chemed, Klallim, Maareches Mem, sec. 61ff.

  52. (Back to text) This indicates that even when it is necessary for a person to have the proper intent, the reason intent is necessary is because that particular mitzvah has some unique characteristic.

  53. (Back to text) See the Shulchan Aruch HaRav (loc. cit.) which states that "not requiring intent" includes "performing the deed without the intent of fulfilling one's obligation, but rather without any intent at all, or with an intent other than that of fulfilling the mitzvah."

  54. (Back to text) See the notes of the Rebbe Rashab to Tanya, ch. 7.

  55. (Back to text) Tanya, ch. 7.

  56. (Back to text) Kiddushin 6a.

  57. (Back to text) Note a similar concept explained in Derech Mitzvosecha, Mitzvos Vidui U'Teshuvah.

  58. (Back to text) Shulchan Aruch HaRav 489:12.

  59. (Back to text) See the maamar entitled U'Reisem, 5666, which states that the desires of the animal soul are separate from each other. Therefore one desire weakens and nullifies another. In contrast, the desires of the G-dly soul are complementary, and each reinforces the other.

  60. (Back to text) Rambam, Mishneh Torah, Hilchos Geirushin 2:20.

  61. (Back to text) The Rambam explains that when a person merely says "I desire" while being compelled by the court, his inner desire rises to the surface, and he is considered to have divorced willingly. When, however, he is compelled to act against the Torah's law, although he says "I desire," he is not considered to have divorced willingly.

  62. (Back to text) Zevachim 6b. See Rashi, entry korbanos, who states that this applies even if the priest who slaughters the sacrifices "does not know what they were intended for." The Rambam's Commentary to the Mishnah (Zevachim 1:1; see also the commentary of Rav Ovadiah of Bartenura) adds a further leniency, saying that this law applies even when the priests sacrificed with the wrong intent in mind.

    This concept is questioned by Menachos 78b. See also the Panim Meiros, Chok Nosan, and other commentaries to Zevachim.

  63. (Back to text) In certain matters, the person must make (even under coercion) a statement of intent, and in others, there is a need to rely on the intent of the court, while in other matters his inner will is expressed through his deed alone. The difference is dependent on the nature of the mitzvah. For example, there are some mitzvos, e.g., prayer, where proper intent is necessary, even after the fact. And there are some mitzvos, e.g., the mitzvos of faith in G-d or love of G-d, which are "obligations of the heart," and dependent totally on our hearts' intent.

  64. (Back to text) Hoshea 2:18. This level represents an advantage over Yeshayahu 54:5 which states: "Your Creator is your Husband," which describes the first stage of the marriage (see Shmos Rabbah, the conclusion of ch. 15). Kesubos 71b explains the verse from Hoshea with the analogy of a bride in her father-in-law's home when familiarity with her husband has already been established.


  ShoftimKi Savo  
   
Volume 6   |   Volume 7   |   Volume 8   |   Volume 9   |   Volume 10
     Sichos In English -> Books -> Parshah -> Likkutei Sichot - Volume X - Devarim
© Copyright 1988-2024
All Rights Reserved
Sichos In English